The Wisdom of the Masses; A Philosophical Case for Elections

By Pomper, Gerald M. | Harvard International Review, Spring 2008 | Go to article overview

The Wisdom of the Masses; A Philosophical Case for Elections


Pomper, Gerald M., Harvard International Review


At first glance, it seems absurd. Why does the modern world choose its leaders through popular elections? Why does the United States think that tens of millions of citizens who do not even know the name of their representatives in Congress can intelligently select the most powerful person on the planet? Or, to take a different country, why do we expect hundreds of millions of Indians beset by poverty to make an informed choice for the leader of the world's second most populous nation?

[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]

The devotion to elections is historically very recent and still not universal. For most of our millennia on earth, rulers--from cavemen to commanders--gained power through physical strength and organized armed might. Their control was legitimized in various ways: the word of God spoken to ancient Israelites, the "Divine Right" of medieval European monarchs, the "Mandate of Heaven" of Chinese emperors. What was originally won by force became accepted through tradition, or what sociologist Max Weber called "the authority of the eternal yesterday."

But authority in today's world requires election to office. The United States and the United Nations do not legitimately accept any government until it has registered its claim to power through a popular vote. That source of legitimacy is acknowledged even by the most autocratic regimes and brutal dictatorships, whether in Hitler's Germany and Stalin's Soviet Union, or in contemporary Russia, Egypt, Myanmar, Zimbabwe, or Cuba.

Why? Political theorists have long attempted to reconcile a normative preference for electoral democracy with the empirical reality that voters are often misinformed, typically disinterested in politics, and largely focused on their private lives. They have been challenged for 2,500 years to rebut Plato's snide description of the "ship of state" in a democracy--a ship on which "the sailors are quarreling over the control of the helm; each thinks he ought to be steering the vessel, though he has never learnt navigation and cannot point to any teacher under whom he has served his apprenticeship; what is more they assert that navigation is a thing that cannot be taught at all, and are ready to tear to pieces anyone who says it can."

Defending Elections

Defenders of elections have a different view. Rejecting Plato's philosophic idealism, they assume the empiricist stance of John Locke and the skepticism of David Hume. Relying on experience, they are wary of claims to power, particularly claims by those who are already powerful and seek protection from anticipated abuses of power. Instead of postulating inherent differences among humans, they envisage developmental possibilities for all people. Democratic theory is ultimately pragmatic, as Winston Churchill concluded: "No one pretends that democracy is perfect or all-wise. Indeed, it has been said that democracy is the worst form of government except all those other forms that have been tried from time to time."

Supporters of electoral choice directly challenge Plato's praise of the elite, presumably qualified helmsmen, and his condemnation of the masses, presumably unqualified sailors. Elites too often sail the ship of state into danger: it was the Bush administration's experts, not the electorates, who engineered US disaster in Iraq. Popular preferences are often right. Even the cynical Machiavelli believed: "It is not without good reason that it is said, 'The voice of the people is the voice of God."' He argued that mass judgments may be better than elite ones: "In the election of their magistrates they make far better choices than princes; and no people will ever be persuaded to elect a man of inferior character and corrupt habits to any post of dignity, to which a prince is easily influenced in a thousand different ways."

Contemporary empirical political science does in fact support some of Machiavelli's optimistic judgment. Richard Lau and David Redlawsk have shown the rationality of the voters, who consistently vote "correctly"--i. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

The Wisdom of the Masses; A Philosophical Case for Elections
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Welcome to the new Questia Reader

The Questia Reader has been updated to provide you with an even better online reading experience.  It is now 100% Responsive, which means you can read our books and articles on any sized device you wish.  All of your favorite tools like notes, highlights, and citations are still here, but the way you select text has been updated to be easier to use, especially on touchscreen devices.  Here's how:

1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
2. Click or tap the last word you want to select.

OK, got it!

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.