Apollo/Dionysus or Heraclitus/Anaxagoras? A Hermeneutic Inquiry into Nietzsche's View of Tragedy

By Devir, Nathan P. | Papers on Language & Literature, Winter 2010 | Go to article overview

Apollo/Dionysus or Heraclitus/Anaxagoras? A Hermeneutic Inquiry into Nietzsche's View of Tragedy


Devir, Nathan P., Papers on Language & Literature


In Nietzschean philosophy, human existence is, in and of itself, a tragedy. Conversely, the nuances of Nietzsche's views on tragedy as an art form are inextricably linked to his philosophy of human existence in general. In other words, looking at human existence as an aesthetic phenomenon is the only viable way in which Nietzsche can reconcile his philosophy of art with his perspective on humanity--the same kind of perspective, incidentally, that is characteristic of the golden age of (Attic) Greek tragedy. And, in agreeing with Aristotle that Greek tragedy represents the highest possible form of artistic achievement, the early Nietzsche states that his objective as a philosopher-poet is "to show how life, philosophy, and art may have a profound relationship to one another without philosophy being shallow or the life of the philosopher filled with lies" (Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks 12). (1)

For further insight into Nietzsche's philosophy of art, the overwhelming majority of scholars have traditionally looked toward The Birth of Tragedy (1872) as the basis from which to interpret Nietzsche's views regarding artistic creation, and tragedy in particular. In The Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche makes the claim that the essential origins of tragedy stem from archaic Greek culture, roughly from the time of Homer (circa 850 B.C.E.) to the middle of the fifth century B.C.E. Nietzsche views the era of Greek history that follows as a period of decadence and decline, starting from Socrates onward. In Socrates, Nietzsche sees the beginning of the end for the Greeks, who were the possessors of what he considers to be humankind's greatest culture. According to Nietzsche, the true manifestation of that culture is to be found in early Greek tragedy--namely, in the dramas of Aeschylus and Sophocles. In contrast, the tragedies of Euripides, which coincide historically and "existentially" with the advent of Socratic thought, stand in stark opposition to the older, more "pure" Hellenic history and therefore do not represent the Greek spirit in all its glory.

The problem with using The Birth of Tragedy as a comprehensive basis for Nietzsche's views on tragedy is, to put it mildly, a multifaceted one. There is no doubt that the book represents an unparalleled innovation with respect to the interpretation of art in the Western tradition; it also, however, may be seen as a perfect example of how not to write a scholarly essay. In addition to his rambling and often incoherent style, Nietzsche does not bother to provide textual citations for many of his sources; further, the lack of critical distance with which he engages the work of Schopenhauer (not to mention Wagner!) leaves little room for a solid, theoretical foundation on which his juxtaposition of the Apollonian and the Dionysian might stand. Most importantly, The Birth of Tragedy uses the pre-Socratic philosophers as its temporal basis for the supposed break in Greek thought, yet it does little more than mention them in passing. For the brilliant classical philologist that Nietzsche was, this lack of detail seems highly curious, if not outright suspect.

That said, this essay will concentrate on the following questions: In Nietzsche's view, what is the precise relationship between the genesis of Greek tragedy and the pre-Socratic philosophers? Is there a hermeneutic--i.e., a methodological approach based on the explanation and interpretation of texts--rather than a mythic or primordial basis to Nietzsche's take on the philosophical origins of tragedy? What would The Birth of Tragedy have looked like had it not been Nietzsche's first book? That is to say: if a similar treatise had been composed at a more mature period in Nietzsche's life, one in which the influence of Richard Wagner was not all-encompassing, would there have been a more concrete basis for his ideas regarding the origins of tragedy, rather than a series of inherently loose suppositions that Nietzsche himself later admitted is, in some respects, simply embarrassing? …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Apollo/Dionysus or Heraclitus/Anaxagoras? A Hermeneutic Inquiry into Nietzsche's View of Tragedy
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.