Philology as Philosophy: The Sources of Ernesto Grassi's Postmodern Humanism

By Rubini, Rocco | Annali d'Italianistica, Annual 2008 | Go to article overview

Philology as Philosophy: The Sources of Ernesto Grassi's Postmodern Humanism


Rubini, Rocco, Annali d'Italianistica


"Gli studi umanistici sono un immergersi nel passato per farlo essere ancora, un additare e un rimembrare: indicare un ricordo. Indicare un ricordo ha in se qualcosa di non chiaro, perche indicare e un dire: 'vedi...'; e ricordare e lo stesso che vedere; indicare e richiamare l'attenzione, e ricordare e gia attendere; e se e gia attendere, perche indicare? e cosa vuol dire poi richiamare l'attenzione, se l'attenzione e gia in atto?"

(Castelli 1)

Current reconsideration of some distinguished Renaissance scholars and postmodern philosophers has renewed both interest in, and controversy surrounding, Renaissance and contemporary humanism(s). The purpose of this essay is to reintegrate Ernesto Grassi's perspective into a debate that has too long suffered from its absence. Those readers who focus on the humanism Grassi developed in the 1980s often conclude that his work, though intriguing, was merely an idiosyncratic reaction to Martin Heidegger's antihumanism. In reality, Grassi's humanism was a complex mediation that engaged with and transcended the estranged worlds of Renaissance scholarship and Continental philosophy. The following essay defines the current context from which Grassi has been excluded, before returning to the philosopher's early career to articulate the foundations of his diffused and gradual approach to the problem of humanism.

Between "umanesimi" and "umanismi"

The major event of the past few years in Renaissance studies is the reconsideration of one of its most distinguished protagonists, Paul Oskar Kristeller. This reappraisal is primarily a concern of American academia, where for fifty years or more Kristeller has been the reigning authority on humanism. The recent investigation of Kristeller's formative years in Germany and Italy and the recovery of his early "philosophical agenda" (Blum 30) has cast doubt on whether his alleged greatest achievement--the "determined historicizing of humanism and Renaissance philosophy" (Hankins, "Kristeller" 138)--was not, after all, tainted by philosophical prejudices. As a younger generation of scholars is ready to admit, Kristeller's allegiance to neo-Kantianism and its commitment to the rationalist tradition of philosophy (from Plato to Kant) may have prevented him from according to humanism its full due as an alternative philosophy.

In turn, a critical recent development in Continental philosophy is an emphasis on the anomaly represented by Hans-Georg Gadamer's work with respect to the mainstream philosophical discourse of his time. Donald P. Verene points out that, besides Ernst Cassirer, "Gadamer is the only thinker of the first order in twentieth-century German philosophy to involve Vico as part of the basis of his thought." If, as Verene believes, "to study Vico is to study humanism and to study what humanism is" (138), Gadamer may count among the few postmodern philosophers not to have shared in Heidegger's unwarranted antihumanism. Similarly, Jean Grondin goes as far as to argue that the question concerning "humanism" is a test to determine "why and at what point a Heideggerian such as Gadamer ceases to be Heideggerian." According to Grondin, Gadamer's Truth and Method should certainly be read as a rejoinder to Heidegger's "Letter on 'Humanism.'" "To put the thesis bluntly," he writes, "Gadamer is a humanist and Heidegger isn't" (157).

It is to his credit that Christopher S. Celenza made a first step toward bridging the long standing divide between Renaissance scholarship and contemporary philosophy. In The Lost Italian Renaissance, Celenza argues that Kristeller's philosophical conservatism has significantly delayed Renaissance scholarship's assimilation of the methodological and epistemological progress made by other disciplines. Indeed, in Celenza's view, the non-Kristellerian attitude toward philosophy held by most twentieth-century thinkers could prove beneficial to the study of humanism and its representatives. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Philology as Philosophy: The Sources of Ernesto Grassi's Postmodern Humanism
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.