The Holmesian Bad Man Flubs His Entrance

By Fried, Barbara H. | Suffolk University Law Review, Summer 2012 | Go to article overview

The Holmesian Bad Man Flubs His Entrance


Fried, Barbara H., Suffolk University Law Review


I. Introduction

Thirty years after its publication, Contract as Promise remains the canonical presentation of a liberal, autonomy-based conception of contractual obligation. In Charles Fried's words, "The moral force behind contract as promise is autonomy: the parties are bound to their contract because they have chosen to be," and their "rights and duties [are] as far as possible a function of their own will and not of standards of justice external to that will." (1) While other strains of liberal contract theory (consent-based, obligation-based) may differ from Prof. Fried's "will" theory of contracts in other respects, they all share his foundational commitment to the view that promissory obligations, unlike most other forms of obligation, are voluntarily assumed. The same is true of most liberal, autonomy-based conceptions of promissory obligation in the moral realm. (2)

The question I wish to pursue here is this: Having established the voluntary nature of promissory obligation, has liberal contract theory (LCT) put itself out of a job? What further role, if any, does it have to play in elaborating the nature and content of promissory obligation?

It clearly has something to say about why promising to do X imposes obligations of some form on the promisor, where a mere expression of a future intention to do X would not. Indeed, of the enormous philosophical literature on promising, the overwhelming majority is addressed to just this question (or so my casual survey suggests). It presumably also has something to say about the preconditions for concluding that a promise was freely, rationally and deliberately--that is, voluntarily--made. This is no small subject, and implicates a host of issues concerning procedural fairness--duty to disclose, misrepresentation, economic duress, etc.--as well as mental capacity.

Finally, LCT does not itself require that the expressed wills of the parties always take precedence over other considerations. In extreme cases, liberal contract theorists could well conclude that those expressed desires should be trumped by paternalistic, public-policy, or fairness considerations. But all of these considerations are, in Prof. Fried's terms, "standards of justice external to that will," and hence not matters on which will theory itself can shed any light. (3)

The question is, does LCT have anything to say about the permissible content of X, beyond saying that parties may give X any content that they wish and courts should, as far as they are able, resolve any dispute between the parties in accordance with the parties' own intentions?

I think the answer is no. Rereading Contract as Promise in full thirty years after its publication, I was surprised to discover that for the most part (the other) Prof. Fried agrees. Much of the book is devoted to two lines of argument, both consistent with that conclusion.

The first line of argument repudiates, as inconsistent with the will theory of contracts, common-law doctrines that override the parties' clear intent. Prof. Fried's treatment of consideration is illustrative here. Acknowledging the irreducible contradiction between "the liberal principle that the free arrangements of rational persons should be respected" and the requirement, embedded in the doctrine of consideration, that in order to be respected those arrangements must include what the law recognizes as a "bargain," Prof. Fried concludes, in effect, so much the worse for the consideration doctrine: "Freedom of contract is freedom of promise, and...the intrusions of the standard doctrines of consideration can impose substantial if random restrictions on perfectly rational projects." (4)

Second, Fried argues that once we are unable to discern the parties' intent, will theory runs out, and any remaining gaps in the contract must be filled by resort to other (external) notions of justice. Prof. Fried's thoughtful treatment of the doctrines governing changed circumstances--mistake, frustration, impossibility, impracticability--is illustrative here.

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

The Holmesian Bad Man Flubs His Entrance
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Welcome to the new Questia Reader

The Questia Reader has been updated to provide you with an even better online reading experience.  It is now 100% Responsive, which means you can read our books and articles on any sized device you wish.  All of your favorite tools like notes, highlights, and citations are still here, but the way you select text has been updated to be easier to use, especially on touchscreen devices.  Here's how:

1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
2. Click or tap the last word you want to select.

OK, got it!

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.