Philosophy and Art in Schelling's System Des Transzendentalen Idealismus

By Dodd, James | The Review of Metaphysics, September 1998 | Go to article overview

Philosophy and Art in Schelling's System Des Transzendentalen Idealismus


Dodd, James, The Review of Metaphysics


In his System des transzendentalen Idealismus, Schelling describes the philosophy of art as the "key stone" of the entire "arch" of the system.(1) The purpose of the following essay is to explore why this is so, why Schelling's idea of philosophy led him to take up the question of "art" not only as philosophically interesting, but as the key to understanding his system as a whole.

That this is an issue in understanding Schelling's System des transzendentalen Idealismus is obvious--in several passages he clearly states that the relation between transcendental reflection and the philosophy of art is decisive. Transcendental philosophy can reach its ultimate goal only when it is in a position to understand the essence of art. Yet what philosophy is actually looking for in art, and what it finds there, is not altogether clear. What does it mean that philosophy, within its own movement of self realization, seeks out something like art, finds it and makes it its own?

In order to answer this question it is necessary to engage in methodological considerations having to do with system building, something already suggested by the architectonic metaphor of "Gewolbe"--that is, considerations of how theoretical and practical philosophy are to be presented as an organic, thus systematic whole. We will leave aside the question of the extent to which in the end such an organic whole is achieved, and instead focus on the philosophical mode as such, the activity of constructing the system. In this way our guiding question will be the origin of transcendental philosophy according to Schelling. This, I believe, is where the key lies in understanding the relation between the philosophy of art and the system as a whole.

The basic thesis runs thus: the reason why the philosophy of art is so important has to do with the mode of reflection that establishes transcendental idealism as a project of thinking. Specifically, the activity of transcendental reflection is comparable to the production of a work of art; thus the task posed by a reflection on "art" is not only that of understanding the aesthetic world, but of understanding philosophy itself.

I

The "Inner City" and the "I." However important the role of art may be in the System des transzendentalen Idealismus, the same is not the case when we turn to Schelling's so-called "identity philosophy," first formulated in 1801. Though the philosophy of art is by no means rejected, it no longer has the decisive significance it had in 1800. This in no way implies, however, that the philosophy of identity has nothing to tell us about the role of art in the 1800 system. The opposite is rather the case, and as illustrative let us cite two passages that express succinctly two themes essential in the interpretation of the System des transzendentalen Idealismus.

The first passage is found in the lectures Schelling held in 1803 under the title Vorlesungen uber die Methode des akademischen Studiums. It appears near the beginning of the fourteenth lecture, which deals with the place of the "sciences of art" in a philosophically grounded curriculum.(2) Right away Schelling confronts what in the philosophical tradition would appear to be the most virulent objection against the inclusion of the study of art in education: Plato's banishment of the poem from the ideal city in the Republic. What can art teach us--so Plato--when it itself, as we philosophers well know, proffers only a false account of the truth? "It is essential," Schelling replies, "to recognize the particular standpoint from which Plato passes this judgment against the poets," namely that Plato is speaking from the standpoint of the "historical, not the philosophical, opposition" between poetry and philosophy. Historically, the poet as educator is the proponent of a "poetical realism," and this is what Plato reacts against: poetics as realism, or the claim that "truth" is itself something sensible, a part of the sensible world. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Philosophy and Art in Schelling's System Des Transzendentalen Idealismus
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Welcome to the new Questia Reader

The Questia Reader has been updated to provide you with an even better online reading experience.  It is now 100% Responsive, which means you can read our books and articles on any sized device you wish.  All of your favorite tools like notes, highlights, and citations are still here, but the way you select text has been updated to be easier to use, especially on touchscreen devices.  Here's how:

1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
2. Click or tap the last word you want to select.

OK, got it!

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.