Democracy and Distrust after Twenty Years: Ely's Process Theory and Constitutional Law from 1990 to 2000

By Boynton, Brian | Stanford Law Review, November 2000 | Go to article overview

Democracy and Distrust after Twenty Years: Ely's Process Theory and Constitutional Law from 1990 to 2000


Boynton, Brian, Stanford Law Review


INTRODUCTION

The Constitution speaks in terse, general language. Yet it is this language that the nine unelected, life-tenured Justices of the Supreme Court must interpret when they strike down democratically produced laws. Judicial review is necessary to safeguard minority rights, but democracy is the principle around which this nation's government was formed. This tension between minority rights and majority role is precisely what John Hart Ely hoped to resolve in his now famous book, Democracy and Distrust.(1) Ely argues that a process-oriented, representation-reinforcing approach to interpreting the Constitution can reconcile these competing interests, and he urges the Supreme Court to follow such an approach.

The goal of this note is to compare the decisions of the United States Supreme Court in the last decade with the outcomes for specific areas of constitutional law that Professor Ely suggests in Democracy and Distrust.(2) I hope to add to the body of scholarship that has critiqued Ely's theory and to shed light on the continuing importance (or unimportance) of Ely's theory to modern constitutional interpretation. Part I will describe Ely's book and theory. Part II will briefly examine the response Ely's work has generated in the academic community, and it will explain where this note fits into that body of work. Finally, Part III will summarize the prescriptions Ely's theory has for specific areas of law and explore the relevant Supreme Court cases from the last decade to see to what extent Ely's prescriptions have been followed.(3)

I. ELY'S THEORY OF CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION

A. Chapter One: The Allure of Interpretivism

Ely opens Democracy and Distrust by introducing the "interpretivism"/ "noninterpretivism" distinction.(4) Interpretivists believe that "judges deciding constitutional issues should confine themselves to enforcing norms that are stated or clearly implicit in the written Constitution" while noninterpretivists think that "courts should go beyond that set of references and enforce norms that cannot be discovered within the four comers of the document."(5) Interpretivists will overturn the work of the political branches only if a law is inconsistent with an inference whose starting point is the text of the Constitution.(6)

Ely finds interpretivism, thus defined, to be attractive for two reasons. First, interpretivism comports with our general notions of statutory interpretation. Second (and more importantly), it is attractive because it is consistent with majoritarian democracy in a way that Ely believes noninterpretivism cannot be.(7) Judicial review of legislation has inherently undemocratic tendencies; it is, after all, the revocation of the will of the majority on the basis of a decision by (in the federal case) life-tenured, unelected judges. But when this revocation finds its basis in the will of the people, as is the case when a judge looks not to natural law, or fundamental values, or some other extra-textual source, but to the text of the Constitution, it can be reconciled with democracy.(8) As Ely puts it: "Thus the judges do not check the people, the Constitution does, which means the people are ultimately checking themselves."(9)

B. Chapter Two: The Impossibility of Clause-Bound Interpretivism

Having just extolled the virtues of interpretivism, Ely turns around and begins to critique it. Interpretivism, at least when a narrow, clause-bound approach is adopted, suggests that "various provisions of the Constitution be approached essentially as self-contained units and interpreted on the basis of their language, with whatever interpretive help the legislative history can provide, without significant injection of content from outside the provision."(10) Unfortunately, this brand of interpretivism, Ely concludes, is fatally flawed because "the constitutional document itself, the interpretivist's Bible, contains several provisions whose invitation to look beyond their four corners--whose invitation, if you will, to become at least to that extent a noninterpretivist--cannot be construed away. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Democracy and Distrust after Twenty Years: Ely's Process Theory and Constitutional Law from 1990 to 2000
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.