Youngstown: Pages from the Book of Disquietude

By Bobbitt, Philip | Constitutional Commentary, Spring 2002 | Go to article overview

Youngstown: Pages from the Book of Disquietude


Bobbitt, Philip, Constitutional Commentary


This essay is dedicated to Lloyd N. Cutler

INTRODUCTION

The Youngstown holding is widely admired. One reads with pride those passages in which the Supreme Court denies to a president with whom they are in considerable political sympathy the power to enlarge executive authority by militarizing the homeland. And yet one wonders, as we confront in the 21st century a lethal foreign enemy who has demonstrated the ability to infiltrate and assault the domestic environment, precisely what restraints ought to govern a presidential response to that enemy.

PART ONE: A MODAL ANALYSIS OF THE YOUNGSTOWN CASE

I. THE FORMS OF ARGUMENT

It is customary among certain theorists to say that there are six forms of argument that supply the rationales for constructions of the constitutional law of the United States. These forms are called the historical (relying on the intentions of the framers and ratifiers of the constitutional provision to be construed), textual (looking to the meaning of the words of the provision alone, as these would be interpreted by the average man in the street today), structural (inferring rules from the relationships that the Constitution as a whole mandates among the various structures it sets up), prudential (seeking to balance the costs and benefits of a particular rule, especially regarding those risks borne by the deciding Constitutional institution), doctrinal (applying rules generated by the precedents that guide a particular constitutional institution) and ethical (deriving rules from the commitments to human rights proclaimed in the Declaration of Independence and the powers to protect those rights reflected in the Constitution). (1)

Sometimes these archetypal forms function as modalities of constitutional law; that is, they make up the ways in which the truth or falsity of a legal proposition is determined, though they are neither true nor false in themselves. There is some debate as to whether there is a hierarchy among these modalities; my own view is that there is not. They are, I would say, incommensurable but not incomparable. (2)

When the rationale for a constitutional decision such as is given in a judicial opinion is described in terms of the modalities employed, it is sometimes said to be the product of modal analysis.

II. MODAL ANALYSIS

Modal analysis calls into question the assumption that justification legitimates law. Many movements and many volumes have been founded on this unquestioned assumption, such as, for example, the notorious pseudo-question called the "Countermajoritarian Objection" which depends upon the alleged deficit in the legitimacy of judicial review that is attributed to its nonconformity with majoritian practices. A good deal of constitutional commentary is an effort to produce justifications for particular holdings or non-judicial decisions on the grounds that such governmental actions lack legitimacy in the absence of non-legal, extra-modal justifications. The increasing irrelevance of, for example, the annual Forewords to the Harvard Law Review--or indeed of law reviews and law journals generally--may in part be laid at the door of the unthinking pursuit of this objective.

Casting off from this assumption permits us to abandon also the idea that the rationale for a decision is--or should be--a recapitulation of the reasons why the decision was reached in the first place. If judicial opinions, for example, are legitimated by certain conventional argumentative practices, then the rationale is an effort to provide guidance for future legitimating occasions--future rationales for future decisions--and not a kind of talking cure for judicial neuroses.

Modal analysis does away with the allegedly fundamental characterization of law as an epiphenomenon, a symptom of extra-legal relations, and replaces this characterization with a description of law as a discrete social activity, no more or less fundamental than other activities that it both shapes and takes shape from. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Youngstown: Pages from the Book of Disquietude
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Welcome to the new Questia Reader

The Questia Reader has been updated to provide you with an even better online reading experience.  It is now 100% Responsive, which means you can read our books and articles on any sized device you wish.  All of your favorite tools like notes, highlights, and citations are still here, but the way you select text has been updated to be easier to use, especially on touchscreen devices.  Here's how:

1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
2. Click or tap the last word you want to select.

OK, got it!

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.