Legal Realism Untamed

By Schauer, Frederick | Texas Law Review, March 1, 2013 | Go to article overview

Legal Realism Untamed


Schauer, Frederick, Texas Law Review


Introduction

Law is not only about hard cases. There are easy ones as well, and understanding law requires awareness not only of litigated and then appealed disputes, but also the routine application of legal rules and doctrine.1 Upon leaving the courthouse and its domain of difficult controversies, we observe the everyday determinacy of law-the production of clear guidance and uncontested outcomes by straightforward legal language, black-letter law, and the conventional devices of legal reasoning.

One consequence of the existence of easy cases along with hard ones is the alleged marginalization of the skeptical challenges of Legal Realism. Legal Realism is conventionally understood, in part, to question legal doctrine's determinacy and positive law's causal effect on judicial decisions.2 But if Realism's skepticism about the constraints of positive law applies only to the sliver of legal events that are litigated cases,3 Legal Realism's challenges can be kept at bay. Realism may remain a valuable corrective to the view that even most appellate cases have a legally right answer, but not as a claim that undermines the routine determinacy of law.4

This marginalization of Legal Realism-its taming, so to speak-turns out, however, to ignore a central Realist theme: the distinction, in Karl Llewellyn's words, between "paper rules," on the one hand, and "real rules," or "working rules," on the other.5 For Llewellyn and other Realists, the crux of their challenge to the traditional view of legal determinacy lay in the fact that the paper rules-the language of statutes and black-letter common law rules-were often poor approximations of the actual rules motivating judicial decisions.6 Judges do follow rules, Llewellyn and most other Realists insisted, but the rules they follow are often not the ones found in standard legal sources.7

The distinction between real and paper rules is well known, but the effect of the distinction upon the supposed marginalization of Legal Realism has remained unnoticed. For when the paper rules do not describe the actual rules that judges use in making decisions, the divergence between paper and real rules will influence the distribution between easy and hard cases. Thus, even if the indeterminacy claims of Realism are limited to the domain of litigated cases, the distinction between paper and real rules determines the makeup of that domain, and accordingly pervades the entirety of law. The gap between paper and real rules, therefore, by producing consequences throughout law and not merely to a small subset of it, reveals the Realist challenge to be more foundational, less marginal, and-importantly-less tamed.

The question I address is as fundamental as it is simple: What makes hard cases hard, and easy ones easy? The answer is empirical, varying with time, place, and area of law. But Legal Realism in its untamed version not only directs us to this question, but also suggests that the answer to the empirical question might, in some contexts and in some domains, challenge the standard view of how law works even in its routine and nonlitigated operation.

I. Legal Realism-Some Basics

The perspective variously known as legal realism, Legal Realism,8 or American Legal Realism9 is widely understood to pose a substantial challenge to a traditional conception of law and legal (especially judicial) decision making. Of course there are almost as many traditional views about legal decision making as there are viewers, but a prominent one holds that official legal materials such as statutes and reported court cases can generate straightforward, mechanical, or logically entailed10 applications in the vast majority of instances.11 And even if the production of legal outcomes is not strictly a matter of syllogistic deduction, a softer version of the traditional view holds that legal outcomes are still the constrained product of legal doctrine and legal materials alone.12 This is roughly the position embodied in the writings of William Blackstone,13 Edward Coke,14 and other celebrants of common law reasoning. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Legal Realism Untamed
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.