Redish on Freedom of Speech

By Alexander, Larry | Northwestern University Law Review, April 1, 2013 | Go to article overview

Redish on Freedom of Speech


Alexander, Larry, Northwestern University Law Review


ABSTRACT-My contribution to this Festschriftfor Marty Redish looks at two of his most important articles on freedom of speech, both published in 1982. One article deals with free speech and advocacy of crime, while the other presents Marty's general justificatory theory of freedom of speech. Although I agree and disagree with various parts of Marty's analysis in the former, I am unpersuaded that Marty's general theory can succeed either positively or normatively. Marty Redish is an important scholar in several domains, displaying enviable versatility as well as depth. Although he is perhaps the leading contemporary expositor of the law of federal jurisdiction, he is almost as important a figure in the vastly more crowded field in which his and my scholarship overlap. Redish on Freedom of Speech is my modest contribution to this richly deserved Festschrift.

I. REDISH ON FREEDOM OF SPEECH: THE BASIC POSITIONS

Marty Redish has written many articles and books on the topic of freedom of speech, but I believe his most important contributions to the topic were two contemporaneous articles that were published thirty years ago. In The Value of Free Speech,1 published in the University of Pennsylvania Law Review, Redish sets forth his view of the basic justifying theory of the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment. And in Advocacy of Unlawful Conduct and the First Amendment: In Defense of Clear and Present Danger,2 published in the California Law Review, Redish recounts the history of the treatment of illegal advocacy under the First Amendment from Schenck v. United States3 to Brandenburg v. Ohio4 and offers his own view on what that treatment should be.

In the Pennsylvania Law Review article, Redish argues that the basic value underlying freedom of speech is that of individual self-realization.5 It is the value that best explains First Amendment doctrine and best justifies the existence of that doctrine. According to Redish, all the values offered as alternatives to self-realization, such as democratic decisionmaking, ultimately derive from individual self-realization and thus presuppose it.6 For example, the value of a democratic system of government rests ultimately on democracy's contribution to individual self-realization, both intrinsically in allowing individuals to control their destinies and instrumentally in developing human faculties that themselves further self-realization. Or so Redish argues.7

In the California Law Review article, Redish examines the important and historically significant corner of free speech doctrine dealing with advocacy of illegal conduct. As can be ascertained from the article's title, Redish endorses the clear and present danger test,8 though not necessarily as it was first elaborated in Schenck9 or later elaborated in Brandenburg.10 For example, Redish rejects the implication in Brandenburg that the speaker must intend the illegal conduct that his words advocate to be validly convicted despite a First Amendment plea in his defense.11 On the other hand, Redish would allow the speaker's conviction only if his words directly, as opposed to indirectly, advocate the illegal conduct, which may or may not be consistent with Brandenburg.12 (I would argue that such a requirement is not a fair implication of Brandenburg.)13

I do not believe Redish succeeds in making his case in either article. Because the article on illegal advocacy is a more localized failure, I shall take it up first.

II. THE DILEMMA OF ADVOCACY OF ILLEGAL CONDUCT

There are three approaches the law might take to speech that could stir an audience to commit crimes. First, the law could focus exclusively on the audience, punishing it and only it for any crimes or attempted crimes it commits as a result of having been stirred to do so by the speaker's words.

Second, the law might attempt, through either the threat of punishment or outright muzzling, to prevent the speaker from uttering the words (or employing other symbols) that might stir the audience to illegality.

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Sign up now for a free, 1-day trial and receive full access to:

  • Questia's entire collection
  • Automatic bibliography creation
  • More helpful research tools like notes, citations, and highlights
  • Ad-free environment

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Redish on Freedom of Speech
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Full screen

matching results for page

Cited passage

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Sign up now to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

"Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited passage

Welcome to the new Questia Reader

The Questia Reader has been updated to provide you with an even better online reading experience.  It is now 100% Responsive, which means you can read our books and articles on any sized device you wish.  All of your favorite tools like notes, highlights, and citations are still here, but the way you select text has been updated to be easier to use, especially on touchscreen devices.  Here's how:

1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
2. Click or tap the last word you want to select.

OK, got it!

Thanks for trying Questia!

Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

For full access in an ad-free environment, sign up now for a FREE, 1-day trial.

Already a member? Log in now.