Academic journal article Harvard International Review

Stepping In

Academic journal article Harvard International Review

Stepping In

Article excerpt

Diplomacy may be the art of statesmanship, but intervention is rarely artful. Whereas diplomacy happens comfortably behind tables, intervention often unfolds dangerously on the ground. Surely one of the most intriguing methods of state-to-state interaction, intervention is also one of the most wide-ranging in form. Many prominent scholars, for example, point to subtle economic and cultural intervention as natural corollaries to liberal trading regimes. Even military interventions may be covert. But intervention is still widely interpreted in its classical, realist sense to mean overt military operations by one state within the borders of another. It is this variety that our symposium seeks to explore.

[ILLUSTRATION OMITTED]

Motives for intervention have varied over the centuries. Geopolitics, for one, has provided a historically powerful impetus for intervention. In the wars preceding the Treaty of Westphalia in 1648, states intervened to diminish the absolute sovereignty and relative material factors of their rivals. Other interventions, as in East Timor in 1999, have focused on creating functional systems of governance. Along with geopolitical justifications are those based on rights. The Rwandan genocide of 1994 sparked debate over whether governments forego their right to sovereignty when they commit crimes against humanity within their own borders. Somewhere between these consequentialist and deontological justifications for intervention lies the institutionalist claim that intervention may occur to uphold international common or positive laws.

All of these justifications betray a certain irony: states wage war to make peace, foster temporary instability for long-term stability, and transgress certain laws to uphold others. On its face, then, the use of force is hardly appealing. So when are these seemingly paradoxical interventions justified? While positivists point to existing international law, liberals appeal to broad consensus on norms or to certain inalienable rights, and realists may argue for the necessity of self-defense. Yet each of these answers raises only more questions. Can international law be natural, wherein states lack absolute freedom to establish their contractual relations? Are there norms outside international law that should govern state-to-state behavior? …

Author Advanced search

Oops!

An unknown error has occurred. Please click the button below to reload the page. If the problem persists, please try again in a little while.