Methods in Philosophy of Education

By Frieda Heyting; Dieter Lenzen et al. | Go to book overview

9

How can philosophy of education be critical? How critical can philosophy of education be?

Deconstructive reflections on children's rights 1

Gert Biesta

Some one will say: Yes, Socrates, but cannot you hold your tongue, and then you may go into a foreign city, and no one will interfere with you? Now I have great difficulty in making you understand my answer to this. For I tell you that to do as you say would be a disobedience to the God, and therefore that I cannot hold my tongue, you will not believe I am serious; and if I say again that daily to discourse about virtue, and of those other things about which you hear me examining myself and others, is the greatest good of man, and that the unexamined life is not worth living, you are still less likely to believe me. Yes I say what is true, although a thing of which it is hard for me to persuade you.

(Plato, Apology: 37e-38a)

Deconstruction, if such a thing exists, should open up.

(Derrida 1987:261)


Introduction

If philosophy of education has reason to exist, it is because it has to perform a critical role vis-à-vis education and vis-à-vis the study of education. Philosophy of education is not there to provide ultimate answers, let alone to lay the foundations for education. It exists to raise questions and to institute doubt. In doing so, philosophy of education remains loyal to the main thrust of Western philosophy which, ever since it has lodged itself in Western culture, has conceived of itself as a critical enterprise.

Socrates is without doubt the main icon of the critical style of philosophy. By a constant questioning of received opinions, he tried to reveal that these could not be sustained as easily as was assumed. Plato translated the Socratic approach into a distinction between knowledge (epistémé) and belief (doxa). This was not only a formalisation of the Socratic style. It also installed a division of tasks - and thereby a distinction - between the common man, who could only achieve doxa, and the philosopher, who could have epistémé, i.e., knowledge of an ultimate reality beyond mere convention and decision.

-125-

Notes for this page

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items
Notes
Cite this page

Cited page

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Buy instant access to cite pages or passages in MLA 8, MLA 7, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Note: primary sources have slightly different requirements for citation. Please see these guidelines for more information.

Cited page

Bookmark this page
Methods in Philosophy of Education
Table of contents

Table of contents

Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this book

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Help
Full screen
Items saved from this book
  • Bookmarks
  • Highlights & Notes
  • Citations
/ 187

matching results for page

    Questia reader help

    How to highlight and cite specific passages

    1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
    2. Click or tap the last word you want to select, and you’ll see everything in between get selected.
    3. You’ll then get a menu of options like creating a highlight or a citation from that passage of text.

    OK, got it!

    Cited passage

    Style
    Citations are available only to our active members.
    Buy instant access to cite pages or passages in MLA 8, MLA 7, APA and Chicago citation styles.

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

    1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

    Cited passage

    Thanks for trying Questia!

    Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

    Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

    Buy instant access to save your work.

    Already a member? Log in now.

    Search by... Author
    Show... All Results Primary Sources Peer-reviewed

    Oops!

    An unknown error has occurred. Please click the button below to reload the page. If the problem persists, please try again in a little while.