Freedom

By Moore, Michael S. | Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy, Fall 2005 | Go to article overview

Freedom


Moore, Michael S., Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy


I. INTRODUCTION

More than two centuries after our Revolution, we Americans are still arguing over the nature, and even the coherence, of three of the natural rights in whose name the Revolution was fought. We contest (because it is also truly contestable in serious ethical discussions) whether the rights to equality (1) and to property (2) are either conceptually coherent or normatively desirable. The same conceptual and ethical queries exist for liberty, conceived of either as a right or as a value: Some contest its conceptual coherence, others pooh-pooh its plausibility as a basic value or as a general right. (3) Such skepticisms about liberty raise several large questions: What is liberty? Why is it valuable? Can there be a general right to liberty?

This short Article can hardly do justice to these three large questions. Nonetheless, in short compass I intend to sketch an answer to each of them.

II. WHAT IS LIBERTY?

"What is ... ?" questions are notoriously fuzzy in what they really seek. When attempting to answer such questions, it is wise for one first to discover what it is that is actually puzzling one. (4) With liberty, our puzzlement is largely normative: What could plausibly be of value and also plausibly be referred to as "liberty" or "freedom"? This suggests that the conceptual question--what do we mean by "liberty"--and the normative question--why is liberty valuable--are like a pair of trousers: Just as we can suspend temporarily putting one leg in while inserting the other, so can we suspend temporarily asking one question while we ask the other. Ultimately we must have one answer that simultaneously satisfies both. What we seek, in other words, is not some concept of liberty that is simply extracted from linguistic or other social practice. Rather, we seek a concept of liberty that at least plausibly names something of interest to us in ethics, something of value such as a good or a right. When we are asking "What is liberty?" we are thus not engaged in conceptual analyses of the old Oxford ordinary language style. We are engaged in a simultaneously normative and descriptive task. (5)

Still, as with trousers, it helps to proceed one leg at a time. What roughly are people typically picking out when they refer to liberty? We have many uses of the word that could serve as our exemplars. Our current President, for example has, in his second term, given numerous "freedom" speeches. Yet such political rhetoric is too overblown for my purposes. Consider a much more mundane example reported recently by the Wall Street Journal. (6) In an article entitled "Risky Riders: Touting Freedom, Bikers Take Aim at Helmet Laws," we hear that ABATE (A Brotherhood Against Totalitarian Enactments) and other motorcyclist lobbyist groups have successfully lobbied twenty-nine states to repeal or modify their helmet requirements for adult motorcycle riders. These groups call their program "five steps to freedom"; they call states where helmets are not required the "free states"; their most successful (and perhaps colorful) lobbyist, Sputnik (his legal name), has the word "FREE" tattooed across his forehead.

It is pretty plain what these motorcyclists intend to refer to by "free" and "freedom": it is the absence of criminal laws requiring them to wear motorcycle helmets. This is the kind of usage of these words that should attract our normative interest. Notice that implicit in this usage are three restrictions: First, that the interest is in negative liberty as absence of constraint; the interest is not immediately, at least, in positive liberty, which is the ability to achieve or obtain something. (7) Second, that the interest is in political liberty, so that the restraint, the absence of which is wanted, is legal coercion. Third, that the specific form of legal coercion to be avoided is criminal sanctions; the liberty desired is part of the principled limits of the criminal law, leaving aside whether other forms of legal coercion or inducements might be acceptable. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Buy instant access to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Freedom
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Help
Full screen

matching results for page

    Questia reader help

    How to highlight and cite specific passages

    1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
    2. Click or tap the last word you want to select, and you’ll see everything in between get selected.
    3. You’ll then get a menu of options like creating a highlight or a citation from that passage of text.

    OK, got it!

    Cited passage

    Style
    Citations are available only to our active members.
    Buy instant access to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

    1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

    Cited passage

    Thanks for trying Questia!

    Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

    Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

    Buy instant access to save your work.

    Already a member? Log in now.

    Oops!

    An unknown error has occurred. Please click the button below to reload the page. If the problem persists, please try again in a little while.