Killing Soldiers

By Overland, Gerhard | Ethics & International Affairs, December 2006 | Go to article overview

Killing Soldiers


Overland, Gerhard, Ethics & International Affairs


A riddle in the ethics of war concerns whether lethal defensive force may be justifiably used against aggressing soldiers who are morally innocent. In this essay I argue that although there might be reasons for excusing soldiers as individuals, one may be justified in using defensive force against them provided that they have initiated threatening behavior and that our interpretation of that behavior as threatening is reasonable. I go on to investigate various implications of being in conflict with aggressing soldiers who are morally innocent, arguing that different restrictions apply to the use of defensive force when the aggressors cannot be held morally responsible for being aggressors.

My argument has important practical implications both for deciding whether to go to war and for deciding how to fight a just defensive war. Concerning the ongoing Iraq war, for example, it suggests that if it were only a matter of killing culpable members of the Republican Guard, invasion could perhaps have been justified. Since any attack would involve killing innocent conscripted soldiers as well as innocent civilians, however, there were good reasons to wait to see whether options other than intervening militarily would become available. If we are engaged in a just defensive war, my argument implies that we must accept a higher level of risk and more harm if we can assume that the aggressors are innocent rather than morally responsible for their harmful or threatening behavior.

Preliminaries

The just war tradition is peculiar in that while its proponents think morality applies to war, they insist that soldiers from each side of a conflict may be justified in killing soldiers from the other side. (1) According to Michael Walzer, a central principle of war is that soldiers have an equal right to kill. (2) In becoming a soldier, one gains the right to kill other soldiers but loses one's immunity against being killed by soldiers of the opposing side. (3) That soldiers defending themselves and their state against unjust aggressors may permissibly have recourse to defensive force is not peculiar; the peculiarity is that, even when just war theory distinguishes between just and unjust sides in a war, it still grants equal rights to kill and liabilities to be killed to each individual soldier, regardless of which side he or she is on.

The implication of granting soldiers an equal right to kill is not immediately clear, however. It could be taken to mean either (or both) that they have a claim against others that they not be prevented from killing, or that they have a privilege to kill--that is, they have no duty not to fight with lethal means. (4) If we say that having a right to do X implies that others must not prevent the doing of X, it would imply that a soldier who is attempting to kill enemy soldiers has a claim against others, including those enemy soldiers, that he or she not be prevented from attempting this killing. But this implication is not very promising. We cannot seriously conceive of soldiers on opposing sides of a war as having parallel claims against each other that they each refrain from preventing the others' attempts to kill them.

Walzer may have had in mind the other element of having a right--namely, that by saying someone has a right to do X, it implies that the person has no duty not to do X. Saying that soldiers fighting an unjust war have a right to kill enemy soldiers could then be taken to mean that soldiers on the unjust side have no duty not to fight the unjust war and kill enemy soldiers. This may seem puzzling as well. It would imply that soldiers fighting for an unjust side have no duty not to kill other soldiers who justly defend themselves against the former's unjust aggression. Consider, as proposed by Jeff McMahan, an unjust combatant who knows that his country's aggressive war is unjust but who decides nonetheless to participate, perhaps because he prefers the risks of combat to the obloquy suffered by peaceniks in his society. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Buy instant access to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Killing Soldiers
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Help
Full screen

matching results for page

    Questia reader help

    How to highlight and cite specific passages

    1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
    2. Click or tap the last word you want to select, and you’ll see everything in between get selected.
    3. You’ll then get a menu of options like creating a highlight or a citation from that passage of text.

    OK, got it!

    Cited passage

    Style
    Citations are available only to our active members.
    Buy instant access to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

    1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

    Cited passage

    Thanks for trying Questia!

    Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

    Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

    Buy instant access to save your work.

    Already a member? Log in now.

    Oops!

    An unknown error has occurred. Please click the button below to reload the page. If the problem persists, please try again in a little while.