Morality in Eighth Amendment Jurisprudence

By Moore, Michael S. | Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy, Winter 2008 | Go to article overview

Morality in Eighth Amendment Jurisprudence


Moore, Michael S., Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy


INTRODUCTION

Morality in Eighth Amendment jurisprudence is but one aspect of a more general topic: the use of moral reasoning by judges in American constitutional interpretation. Seeing the role of moral reasoning through the prism of the Eighth Amendment may help shed light on the more general topic because of three facts: a clear historical record about the Amendment, its frequent invocation in theoretical debates about morality and jurisprudence, and the way it has forced the Supreme Court to address morality directly in its opinions.

We know a great deal about the history of the Eighth Amendment. We know precisely what kind of debate surrounded the provisions that ultimately led to the adoption of the Cruel and Unusual Punishment Clause. (1) We also have a fairly specific understanding of what penalties were thought to be acceptable under the Clause at the time of its adoption. A sufficient historical record is thus available to interpret the Clause for those who choose to do so because they adhere to a narrow intentionalist theory of constitutional interpretation (as did the Justice Department under Ed Meese (2)). We know, for example, that the application of the death penalty to juveniles-the issue considered in Roper v. Simmons (3)--was considered acceptable so long as the defendants were at least seven years old. (4) If original intent and history are important to a judge, a thorough record is available for use.

In part because of the extensive historical record, the Eighth Amendment has opened the door to extensive debate over so-called "interpretive intent," drawing in such theorists as Paul Brest, (5) Ronald Dworkin, (6) Raoul Berger, (7) and H. Jefferson Powell. (8) These scholars often refer to the Cruel and Unusual Punishment Clause because the debates at the time of adoption allow competing sides to make arguments about whether the Framers intended the clauses of the Constitution to be interpreted by their own intentions. As a result, Eighth Amendment jurisprudence is comparatively well theorized.

Finally, throughout Supreme Court opinions interpreting the Clause--from Weems v. United States, (9) to Justice Stewart's opinion in Gregg v. Georgia, (10) to Justice Kennedy's opinion in Roper (11)--one finds Justices who are self-conscious about their use of moral reasoning in their jurisprudence. The Court's Eighth Amendment opinions, like those under the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, are miniature essays in judicial philosophy, so Eighth Amendment interpretation is already theorized as a moral enterprise by the judges who have interpreted it. The Eighth Amendment is therefore a good illustration of the general topic of morality in constitutional interpretation.

A longer article might have discussed what elements besides moral reasoning go into constitutional interpretation. For example, some jurists turn to the history surrounding adoption of the Constitution, mining it for either the intentions of the Framers or the beliefs of their original audience. Others turn to Supreme Court precedent, to the semantics of the constitutional text, or to its pragmatics in the context of its utterance. Some judges find a place for default rules, which Judge Frank Easterbrook calls, in a different context, "tiebreakers." (12) These are just a few of the many things a complete theory of interpretation might include. (13)

For this Essay, I focus only on the role of moral reasoning in constitutional interpretation, analyzing this important factor through the lens of the Cruel and Unusual Punishment Clause of the Eighth Amendment. In particular, the Essay pursues three aspects of this topic: first, whether constitutional interpretation is, can, or should be value-free; second, what the sources of values might be for judges when they look to values in their constitutional interpretation; third, whether judges doing such interpretation should ever rely on their own valuations. …

The rest of this article is only available to active members of Questia

Already a member? Log in now.

Notes for this article

Add a new note
If you are trying to select text to create highlights or citations, remember that you must now click or tap on the first word, and then click or tap on the last word.
One moment ...
Default project is now your active project.
Project items

Items saved from this article

This article has been saved
Highlights (0)
Some of your highlights are legacy items.

Highlights saved before July 30, 2012 will not be displayed on their respective source pages.

You can easily re-create the highlights by opening the book page or article, selecting the text, and clicking “Highlight.”

Citations (0)
Some of your citations are legacy items.

Any citation created before July 30, 2012 will labeled as a “Cited page.” New citations will be saved as cited passages, pages or articles.

We also added the ability to view new citations from your projects or the book or article where you created them.

Notes (0)
Bookmarks (0)

You have no saved items from this article

Project items include:
  • Saved book/article
  • Highlights
  • Quotes/citations
  • Notes
  • Bookmarks
Notes
Cite this article

Cited article

Style
Citations are available only to our active members.
Buy instant access to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

(Einhorn, 1992, p. 25)

(Einhorn 25)

1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

Cited article

Morality in Eighth Amendment Jurisprudence
Settings

Settings

Typeface
Text size Smaller Larger Reset View mode
Search within

Search within this article

Look up

Look up a word

  • Dictionary
  • Thesaurus
Please submit a word or phrase above.
Print this page

Print this page

Why can't I print more than one page at a time?

Help
Full screen

matching results for page

    Questia reader help

    How to highlight and cite specific passages

    1. Click or tap the first word you want to select.
    2. Click or tap the last word you want to select, and you’ll see everything in between get selected.
    3. You’ll then get a menu of options like creating a highlight or a citation from that passage of text.

    OK, got it!

    Cited passage

    Style
    Citations are available only to our active members.
    Buy instant access to cite pages or passages in MLA, APA and Chicago citation styles.

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn, 1992, p. 25).

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences." (Einhorn 25)

    "Portraying himself as an honest, ordinary person helped Lincoln identify with his audiences."1

    1. Lois J. Einhorn, Abraham Lincoln, the Orator: Penetrating the Lincoln Legend (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1992), 25, http://www.questia.com/read/27419298.

    Cited passage

    Thanks for trying Questia!

    Please continue trying out our research tools, but please note, full functionality is available only to our active members.

    Your work will be lost once you leave this Web page.

    Buy instant access to save your work.

    Already a member? Log in now.

    Author Advanced search

    Oops!

    An unknown error has occurred. Please click the button below to reload the page. If the problem persists, please try again in a little while.